(Prague 2010)
You may also want to visit The propagation of non-propagation
Historically informed anti-natalism
History has laid down for all to see the good things and the bad things which people can enjoy and must endure and the atrocities which some people can administer to many others. Presumably, most of the good and bad things will not disappear if we move into the future by ten, a hundred or a thousand years. However, there would be no people at all in the future to experience the good and the bad things if people ceased to procreate as from today. I suggest people should refrain from procreation as the good things in life do not compensate for the bad things and, first and foremost, the best things do not compensate for the worst things.
The experience of unspeakable pain, the agonies of the wounded, sick or dying are not counterbalanced by the delight the sufferer experienced earlier in life; nor is the suffering of the inmates of concentration camps neutralized by many contemporary peoples’ well-being.
The part played by philosophy in the whole of culture amounts to that of an immune system. Where pro-natal religion has set out on the retreat, philosophy is there to keep at bay what one may label the luring gnostic temptation: to abstain from procreation in order to prevent future suffering. In such metaphysical systems as
the thought of the Church Fathers, Kant's teleology, Marxism, positive utilitarianism, R. M. Hare’s prescriptivism or
the ontologies of Nicolai Hartmann and Hans Jonas, it ascribes a mission to man, anchoring him in Dasein. In my books SOLL EINE MENSCHHEIT SEIN? / OUGHT MANKIND TO EXIST? (1995) and VEREBBEN DER MENSCHHEIT?
/ EBBING AWAY OF MANKIND? (2000) I demonstrate how philosophy failed in its endeavour to secure man a metaphysical place in the universe. Without such a place, however, procreation becomes ruinous and selfish.
If philosophy is the brain of religion, then anti-natalism is the neocortex of
philosophy. In the guise of the question OUGHT MANKIND TO EXIST? the human
spirit offers evidence of its having reached the age of discretion. No matter
how much man may be his own product, he originally was, and at least in part
still is, a product of natural lottery. By virtue of the moral theory of
anti-natalism man testifies to his capability of self-liberation from the
presettings of a natural heritage which still permeate our existence.
Anti-natalism is man's emergence from immaturity which is equally imposed upon
him by nature and self-incurred.
I am not of the opinion that coming into existence goes along with being harmed, nor does coming into existence go along with a benefit – as harms and benefits presuppose the existence of the respective human being. However, I am convinced that once we are here we will experience severe harm and that many of us will harm others.
To my mind, a universe void of sentient creatures is neither good nor bad. In my judgement, it is ethically neutral. Consider: The first sentient being comes into existence. In scenario A its first sensation is pleasure, whereas in scenario B its first sensation is pain. In my view, a hitherto neutral universe is rendered good in scenario A whereas it becomes bad in scenario B.
Some philosophers claim an asymmetry according to which a universe in wich pain is absent is good while a universe in which pleasure is absent is not bad. In my judgement, pain and pleasure would be symmetrical here: If a universe is deemed good because there is no one in it who experiences pain, then, by the same token, a universe would have to be labelled bad, if there is no one in it to experience pleasure. I do not, however, accept this logic. Consider a universe that, day by day, contains less pain (fewer sentient beings who experience less pain or less severe pain). Such a universe becomes better and better until – at a certain point in time – it has become ethically neutral. This occurs when the last sentient being has ceased to exist. Such a universe might be amenable to aesthetic judgement, but not to ethics.
Is there a moral reason to procreate with respect to the pleasure one’s offspring would experience? I think not.
Is there a moral reason not to procreate regarding the pain one’s offspring would experience? I think the answer should be
yes.
Why is this so? Apparently, pleasure and pain do not count equally. Pain seems to weigh more, ethically speaking, than pleasure. This seems to be confirmed if we move to decisions and their reversal. Consider couple C who have decided not to procreate as they think their children would be miserable because of their genetic disposition. One day they are informed this was wrong. Their children would be extremely well off. Now consider couple D who have decided to procreate because they think their children would lead happy lives. One day they are informed their children would suffer extreme pain from the first day on. Apparently there is more reason for couple D to reverse their decision than there is for couple C. Which is to say: Expected pain outweighs expected pleasure by far. In ethics, pleasure and pain do not seem to be on a par.
The slaughterhouse clarification
People who come into existence are not harmed by their coming into existence. Rather, the existence of
people or other conscious beings is a prerequisite for there to be harm. I would even admit that some people lead good lives. Nonetheless I am an anti-natalist, and I do recommend to reverse any pro-natal decision on the grounds that many people will suffer unspeakably even though all parents might have only good intentions regarding their offspring: The
pleasure parents derive from having children and the bliss some people experience in life are inextricably interwoven with the pain countless other people (and non-human sentient beings) experience. Let me clarify this with respect to the institution of the slaughterhouse: The
pleasure most people derive from eating meat is inextricably interwoven with intense suffering on the part of the animals that are raised and slaughtered. The animals’ suffering is not compensated for by the fun most people experience when they eat meat. Pointing to some animals that have decent lives and are killed painlessly is to no avail. In a similar manner, the
joy that a considerable
number of people experience in their lives is built upon an ocean of suffering. As every procreation implies a lottery (genetically and socially) and as history has revealed to us what man is capable of doing to his counterpart, any decision to procreate should be reversed. – While there is no such reason to reverse a decision not to procreate regarding those few who would presumably lead decent lives and die pain- and
fearlessly.
(Old Delhi, October 2011)
My
books and articles on anti-natalism
Books:
Antinatalismus
Ein Handbuch
2017
Verebben
der Menschheit?
Neganthropie und Anthropodizee
Freiburg
2000
Soll
eine Menschheit sein?
Eine fundamentalethische Frage
Cuxhaven / Dartford 1995
Chapter in book:
Antinatalist Manifesto
(English translation 2018. German version published in 2014)
Is
Vegetarianism an Antinatalism?
(English translation 2018. German version
published in 2014)
Kurnig
- the first modern antinatalist
2018
In: pro iure animalis, July 2014
In: Tabula Rasa. Zeitung für Gesellschaft und Kultur, April 2014
Ehrfurcht vor dem Leben und Vermehrungsfurcht.
Für einen tierlichen Antinatalismus
In: pro iure animalis, 22 April 2014
In: pro iure animalis, 24 March 2014
Fiel Thomas
Bernhard einem Verbrechen zum Opfer?
In: Tabula Rasa. Zeitung für Gesellschaft
und Kultur, February 2014
Gandhis Gangart
In: Tabula Rasa. Zeitung für Gesellschaft
und Kultur, December 2013
Morgenländische
Niegewesenseinswünsche. Eine Eloge auf Omar Chayyam
In:
Tabula Rasa. Zeitung für Gesellschaft und Kultur, May 2013
Existenzgeld.
Für ein bedingungsloses nativistisches Grundeinkommen
In:
Tabula Rasa. Zeitung für Gesellschaft und Kultur, April 2013
Von
der Existenzverwünschung zur Daseins-Anklage.
Antinatalismus in Georges Poulets unbekanntem Meisterwerk
Rien n'est...
In:
Tabula Rasa. Zeitung für Gesellschaft und Kultur, January 2012
Seinsunwilligkeit
vor dem Schleier gebürtlichen Nichtwissens
Von John Rawls zu Samuel Butler
In:
TABVLA
RASA. JENENSER ZEITSCHRIFT FÜR KRITISCHES DENKEN, April 2011
Antinatalismus
und letzte Menschen in der Literatur -
Erinnerung an einen vergessenen Roman Karl Ettlingers (1882-1939)
In:
Tabula Rasa. Die Kulturzeitung aus Mitteldeutschland, October
2010
Theodicy
shading off into Anthropodicy in Milton, Twain and Kant
Antinatalism as Eve’s Escape Route in
the Face of Wrongful Creation, Unrequested Existence and the Evil of Freedom
In:
Tabula Rasa. Die Kulturzeitung aus Mitteldeutschland, March
2010
The
End and the Permanence of Mankind in Karl Jaspers’s Philosophy
In: Jahrbuch der Österreichischen
Karl-Jaspers-Gesellschaft 1999, p. 83-103
Reviews:
Julio Cabrera:
Zur Wertschaffung verurteilt – Julio Cabreras Buch DISCOMFORT AND MORAL
IMPEDIMENT
Tabula Rasa, February 2019
Der letzte Messias.
Ligottis "The Conspiracy against the Human Race"
Thomas Ligotti, The Conspiracy against the
Human Race. A Contrivance of Horror,
Hippocampus Press, New York 2010, 246 S.
ISBN 978-0-9824296-9-3
In: Tabula Rasa. Zeitung für Gesellschaft und Kultur,
October 2013
Jim Crawford:
Confessions of an Antinatalist
Nine-Banded Books 2010, ISBN 978-1616583453, 12 $
In:
Tabula Rasa.
Zeitung für Gesellschaft und Kultur,
March 2011
David Benatar:
Vom Schaden
des Existenzbeginns.
Ein
Rezensions-Essay zu David Benatars
"Better never to have been. The harm of coming into existence"
Oxford University Press 2006
In: Tabula
Rasa. Jenenser Zeitschrift für Philosophie Nr. 36 (2/2009)
[Page added 2 May 2011. Modified 5 May 2019]