Abstract:
The terms “existence” and
“permanent non-existence” convey in a more precise fashion what is usually
conveyed by the predicates “alive” and “dead” and their derivates. When used
non-metaphorically, “alive” is a predicate that conveys the information that an
entity of a certain kind has not permanently ceased to exist. The entity in
question is a living being. Inasmuch as I have no doubt that I exist, I should
have no doubt that I am a living being. Essentially, I am an embodied mind that
is generated by my brain. Once I was a pre-personal living human being without
a first-person perspective and I might end up as a post-personal human being. I
cease to exist permanently when my brain permanently ceases to generate
consciousness. For a living being to have ceased to exist forever is to be
dead. What remains after a living being has died is not a dead body but the
body of a living being that has ceased to exist forever. If a functioning
organism remains after I have ceased to exist forever (as in the brain-death
constellation), this organism would not constitute a living being. It would be
the functioning organism that formerly constituted myself, the living being.
Before I came into existence there was a functioning organism that later
constituted myself and became my organism. Organisms that constitute living
beings are alive only derivatively. This amounts to a mentalistic definition of
“living being”, “end of a life”, “beginning of a life”.
A
definition of life
What does it take to achieve a non-arbitrary definition of the terms
“living being”, “death” and “beginning of a life”? A chapter in revisionary
ontology
1.
We should be able to agree on at least one specimen/example for the term
“living being”.
There is some dispute on the question of whether or not viruses should
count as living beings. There is less dispute as regards plants. There seems to
be no dispute at all with respect to people, such as you and me, author and
reader of these lines. At least you and I are living beings. This assertion is
more than an intuition; it is a condition for meaningful description[1]
with respect to our place in the physical and social world.
2.
We should be able to agree on the assumption that “death” is a term that refers
to the permanent end of the existence of a living being.
We should rule out metaphorical usage of the term “death”. Many things
irreversibly pass out of existence. Some people use the term “death” to refer
to the irreversible existence of entities other than living beings, such as
“sun” or “flame”. If we do not restrict ourselves to non-metaphorical usage of
the term “death”, all aspirations of coming to grips with a definition are in
vain.
3.
We should be able to determine what a living being is essentially. In order to
do so we will have to ask: which is the property I or you cannot lose without
irreversibly ceasing to exist? If we know what a living being is essentially,
we can determine what living beings, in general, are essentially.
These lines were written or are being read by a living being that is a
person, as the content of these lines is accessible only to beings that are
self-aware. Are we essentially persons and do we cease to exist irreversibly
when we lose the qualities or abilities usually ascribed to persons? There is a standard test, the Avoidance
of Future Great Pain Test[2],
that may elicit an answer: would you, named XY, as a self-interested rational
person, invest today financial means in order to prevent substantial pain that
an Alzheimer’s patient, named XY, with a brain in decay will suffer inevitably
in years to come if you do not invest those means today? The question is meant
to elicit an answer to the question: would that patient, who doesn’t even
remember his name or recognize his relatives, be you or someone else? Is it you
who continues to exist although Alzheimer’s has eradicated all memories; or is
it someone else who came into existence as all memory vanished? Depending on
whether or not you assume that you are identical with Alzheimer’s patient XY
in, say, 11 years, you will or will not invest (provided you act today as a
self-interested actor). I, for one, would invest since I am convinced that the
pain would be felt by me who would continue to exist as a post-personal
being – even though I would not know who I am. If I were XY, I would invest
because I am convinced that I would persist through the loss of personhood.
To many, Avoidance of Future Great Pain Tests reveal that I am
not essentially a person. This conclusion is supported if I look backwards: I
did not come into existence as a person but developed personhood gradually.
Before I became a person, I was a sentient foetus that eventually was born as a
sentient baby. Hence, I understand “person” as a phase sortal.
Therefore, generally speaking, what I am essentially seems to be a mind
that is supported by specifically organised matter without which it couldn’t
exist. I am an embodied mind. If I am a living being and if what I am
essentially is an embodied mind, then any entity that essentially is like me
counts as a living being.
4.
Once we know what living beings are essentially, we will be able to determine
when they cease to exist forever.
If I am essentially an embodied mind, I may lose the first-person
perspective and continue to exist. Likewise, as an embodied mind, I might even
lose 97% of my body – I presumably wouldn’t cease to exist as long as those 3%
of my body that are essential in order to generate my mind persist and function
properly. A living being ceases to exist forever when the bodily
presuppositions of a mind irreversibly cease to be given.
5.
Once we know when a living being ceases to exist forever, we will be able to
determine when the existence of a living being begins.
If I cease to exist forever when my brain ceases to generate
consciousness forever, then, symmetrically, I began to exist when my brain
supported consciousness for the first time. Generally speaking: a new living
being comes into existence when an organism or a brain or other material
processes generate consciousness.
6.
These tasks fulfilled, we should be able to give a definition of the term
“living being”.
I, as a living being, began to exist when my brain generated
consciousness for the first time. I will have ceased to exist forever (in
common language: I will “be dead”) when my brain has permanently ceased to
generate consciousness (note: my brain might permanently have ceased to
generate consciousness without, under certain conditions, having irreversibly
ceased to generate consciousness. One might reasonably say that my brain
retains the capacity to generate consciousness when deep frozen. However, if I
am in a deep frozen condition on board a space ship that went out of control,
the people on earth will say that I died when my brain permanently ceased to
generate consciousness even though it might retain a capacity to do so). This
allows for reversible non-existence: if my brain intermittently generates no
consciousness at all (as perhaps in a deep sleep or coma or deep-frozen
condition), then I would intermittently not exist . I would intermittently not
exist without being intermittently dead; as “death” refers to permanent
non-existence. The span of my existence, my lifespan, is tantamount to the time
during which my brain generates consciousness. As other minds might not be
generated by brains, but by other organs or even by the organism as a whole (as
is perhaps the case with unicellular organisms) or by electronic systems, a
definition of living being will amount to: a living being is a mind that
is being generated by properly organised matter.
If the intension
of the term “living being” can be formulated as “an embodied mind” or “a mind
that is generated by processing matter”, then the extension of the term “living
being” includes all entities that are embodied minds.
7.
Although we have been able to offer an apparently non-arbitrary definition of
the term “living being”, we still have to agree on the following: we should
rule out the acceptability of two or more definitions side by side. A
definition is a definition by virtue of its comprising all entities a certain
term is referring to. Where there are two or more definitions for one and the
same term – two different intensions with two different extensions – the task
of defining the term has not been carried out properly.
Versions of an embodied-mind account of our survival/of identity and, by
the same token, of the existence of living beings[3]
are defended by quite a few philosophers, and it seems more popular than
organismic accounts of identity[4].
To my knowledge, however, all of these philosophers juxtapose and resort to two
definitions of the term “living being”. For them, the intension of the term
“living being” is twofold. First and foremost, they regard all embodied minds
as living beings, an implication of which is: I am a living being. On the other
hand, they view all functioning – though mindless – organisms as living beings,
an implication of which is: before I began to exist/to live, the functioning
organism – that later became my body – was a living being. However, this fails to adequately come to grips with a
definition of the term “living being”. There is a first definition of the term living being: every entity that
is an embodied mind is a living being. And there is a second definition of the
term living being: every entity that is a functioning organism is a living
being.
Proponents of the embodied-mind account of identity/survival tend to
juxtapose two definitions of the term “living being” because they are at a loss
when it comes to the ontology of what we may call pure – that is:
mindless – functioning organisms. In the embodied-mind account of living
beings, there was a pure organism before I came into existence, before my life
began. Symmetrically – as is the case with brain-death – there might be a
functioning pure organism after I have irreversibly ceased to exist. Some
proponents of an embodied-mind account of identity endorse that the latter pure
organism is a living being although I have ceased to exist forever[5].
After what has been outlined above, however, a pure organism should not
count as a living being, since we found that living beings are entities, which
is what you and I most fundamentally are. Most fundamentally, you and I, who
doubtlessly are living beings, are embodied minds, but not pure organisms. If
this is the case, then pure organisms must be ruled out from the extension of the
term “living being”.
8.
We will have to face the consequences of the mentalistic definition of the term
“living being” and of the end and the beginning of a life
Some will have difficulties in accepting the consequences of this
supposedly non-arbitrary definition of the term “living being” because its
philosophical implications contravene some of our bedrock intuitions: if pure
organisms do not count as living beings, then it would be inappropriate to talk
about the life, death and killing of plants, early embryos and of the
functioning bodies of the deceased, i.e. the brain-dead. The question is:
should our intuitions override our arguments? A good case in point is the
definition of the term “planet” that was endorsed by the International
Astronomers’ Union in 2006. The intension of the actual definition of the
term “planet” is such[6]
that Pluto does not belong to the extension of the term whereupon it lost its
former status as a planet[7].
My mentalistic definition of
the terms “living being”, “end of a life” and “beginning of a life” can be used
to answer a looming question that haunts those who assume there is a living
organism before I begin to exist and after I have died in a brain-death
constellation: were there two living beings, myself as a living being, and my
functioning organism as a second living being? A powerful philosophical tool to
address this riddle is the Constitution View, a main proponent of which is Lynn
Baker. According to Baker’s account of the Constitution View, you and I are
essentially persons (beings with a first-person-perspective) that are
being constituted by our living organisms. As she explains, my organism is a
person only derivatively, while I am a person essentially. Hence,
I cease to exist forever when I cease to exist as a person. According to Baker,
I am dead when I cease to exist as a person[8].
And if I go into an irreversible coma, what remains is a living organism that
had previously constituted myself, the living person. When this happens, Baker
explains, the living organism is “precipitated out”[9].
The metaphysics of this “precipitating out” seems unfathomable and would need
further explanation in order to become convincing[10].
Despite this, the idea of the constitution-relation proves helpful: in my
account I am constituted by a body, a functioning organism (or, more precisely,
by a brain that functions sufficiently). In opposition to Baker and proponents
of other versions of the embodied-mind account of identity, I claim that what
remains when I irreversibly cease to exist in a brain-death constellation is
not a living organism. Rather, it is the functioning organism that (or: whose
brain) constituted me. I was the living being. The organism (the brain
as long as it generated consciousness) constituted me, the living being. Doing
so, the organism was a living being (an embodied mind) only derivatively, while
I was an embodied mind (a living being) essentially. Even though functioning
organisms constitute living beings, they are essentially not.
Literature
Akerma, Karim: 2006, Lebensende und Lebensbeginn.
Philosophische Implikationen und mentalistische Begründung des
Hirn-Todeskriteriums, Lit Verlag, Hamburg
Baker, Lynne Rudder:
2000, Persons and
Bodies. A Constitutional View,
Cambridge University Press
Benatar,
David: 2006, Better Never to have been. The Harm of Coming into Existence,
Oxford University Press
Ford, Norman: 1988, When Did I Begin?,
Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Gervais, Karen Grandstrand: 1986, Redefining
Death, Yale University Press, New Haven and London
Green, Michael
B./Wikler, Daniel: 1980, Brain Death and Personal Identity, in: Philosophy & Public Affairs 1980, 9, no. 2,
pp. 105-133
Liao, S. M.: 2006, The Organism View
Defended, in: The Monist 2006; 89 (3), pp. 334-350
Lizza, John P.: 2006,
Persons, Humanity, and the Definition of Death, The John Hopkins
University Press, Baltimore
Lockwood, Michael:
1985, When does a
Life Begin?, in: M. Lockwood
(ed.): Moral Dilemmas in Modern Medicine. Oxford University Press 1985, pp.
9-31
McMahan, Jeff: 2002, The Ethics of Killing. Problems at the Margins of Life, Oxford University Press
Olson, Eric T.: 1997,
The Human Animal.
Personal Identity Without Psychology, Oxford University Press, New York-Oxford
Unger, Peter: 1990, Identity, Consciousness & Value, Oxford University Press 1990
Unger, Peter: 2000, The
Survival of the Sentient, in: Noûs, Volume 34,
Supplement 4, October 2000 , p. 325-348
Zinkernagel,
Peter: 1962, Conditions for Description, Humanities Press, New York
[1] For an analysis of conditions for
description cf. Zinkernagel (1962)
[2] Cf. Unger (1990, 27ff and 2000).
[3] At this point it may be justified
to substitute the common expression “the embodied mind account of
survival/identity” by “the embodied-mind account of living beings”. The
embodied-mind account of survival/identity is always aimed at as an account of
the conditions of the survival of a living being. Therefore, my alteration
seems justifiable.
[4] Among them are
Green/Wikler (1980, 107), Lockwood (1985, 11), Gervais (1986, 2), Unger (1990,
7), Baker (2000, 18f), McMahan (2002, 4), Lizza (2006, 13). According to
organismic accounts of identity a living being is most fundamentally a
functioning organism. This account of identity is held, among others, by Ford,
Olson and Liao. Benatar’s account of our survival/identity is ambivalent: “…
each one of us was once a zygote…” (2006, 134), but as a zygote we did not yet
exist in a morally relevant sense. According to Benatar, a living being comes
into existence in a morally relevant sense when an organism, being conscious,
has interests (cf. l.c. 133ff).
[5] Lizza calls it “a ‘humanoid’ or
‘biological artifact,’… a form of life created by medical technology.” (2006,
15)
[6] “A ‘planet’ is a celestial body
that (a)is in orbit around the Sun, (b) has sufficient mass for its
self-gravity to overcome rigid body forces so that it assumes a hydrostatic
equilibrium (nearly round) shape, and (c) has cleared the neighbourhood around
its orbit.” (http://www.iau.org/public_press/news/release/iau0603/) Viewed
2009-03-01, 14:56 GMT
[7] Some people even took to the street
in order to voice their discontent with the newly established definition and
Pluto’s ensuing loss of planethood (cf. New Scientist, 21 January 2009).
[8] There is an asymmetry in her
account since she claims that I existed well before I displayed the abilities
typical for a person. Baker would parry this reproach saying that I have always
been a person; already as a newborn I allegedly was a person because I evolved
towards a person. By comparison, an ape, whose cognitive capacities are
paramount to mine when a baby, is not a person on her account.
[9] “Although a human person has a
single life that incorporates organic life, it is metaphysically possible to
»precipitate out« an organic life that is not personal…” (Baker, 19)
[10] According to the Constitution View
as defended by Baker, “if my mother had miscarried when she was five months
pregnant with the fetus that came to constitute me, I would never have
existed.” (Baker, 204) At the same time she claims that, most fundamentally, I
am a person and that, because of the potentiality, persons exist as such
even before first-person perspective is achieved: “To be a person… one must
have the capacity for a first-person perspective.” (Baker, 92) And: “… a normal
newborn human is (i.e., constitutes ) a person.” (l.c.) Furthermore: “So, from
birth, development of a first-person perspective is underway” (l.c., note).
Here, we are at a loss as regards the question whether or not we existed when
the five-months-old sentient fetus existed. On one occasion Baker claims it
wasn’t me. At the same time, however, she has it that the mere capacity for a
first-person perspective is sufficient for there to be a person. Baker’s
general problem is with the ontology of living beings that are neither pure
organisms nor persons.